Search This Blog

Sunday, 9 September 2018

The Categorial Ontology of John Bigelow and Martin Leckey. Part 1: A possible problem with Vagueness?

Being a relative novice about categorial ontologies, but with some interest in, and experience with, lambda calculus, I was very interested in a paper about a categorial ontology presented by John Bigelow and Martin Leckey at the 2018 NZAP conference (at which conference I also enjoyed presenting).

Categorial ontologies that accompany formal category languages are ontologically prolific. They are ontologically inflationary compared to the ontologies of particulars familiar from first order formal logic. Normally associated with categorial logical languages, categorial ontologies admit to the ontology as real universals, properties and relations, in addition to the extensional particulars or individuals admitted by first order formal logic. The categorial ontology proposed by John Bigelow and Martin Leckey both countenances, and admits to the furniture of the world, properties and relations. It also admits properties of properties, properties of relations, relations between relations, relations between properties, properties of properties of properties, and so on, recursively - in what John Bigelow recently called 'worlds without end'.

Thus an important element of adherence to a categorial ontology like that of Bigelow and Leckey is a commitment to realism about more than just particulars or individuals, and universals:

Bigelow, J and Leckey, M. Categorial Ontology, Presented at the 2018 NZAP Conference at Wellington University of Victoria.

In their 2018 NZAP presentation, Bigelow and Leckey identified as a motivation the quandary faced by W.V.O Quine with respect to universals. Quine was determinedly anti-realist about universals, but, in accordance with the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument, begrudgingly acceded to the inclusion of abstract mathematical particulars in the furniture of the world. This made Quine both nominalist about universals and - in a certain sense - realist: a very nearly contradictory position - if not a full-blown contradiction. According to The Quine-Putnam indispensability argument, abstract mathematical particulars get referred to in our best and most effective scientific theories with apparent realist commitments, and so the positivist and/or scientistic philosopher should bow to scientific intuition and practice and admit abstract mathematical entities into the ontology, realist-wise.

Syntax and Semantics


Due to these ontological commitments, formal categorial languages like that of Bigelow and Leckey have certain syntactic requirements. Bigelow and Leckey's categorial ontology comes with a very clean notation inspired by the work of M.J. Cresswell (Monash University associate of Bigelow) who adapts the work of Polish logician Stanislaw Lesniewski

The first semantic challenge for the formal categorial language designer is deciding what to assign the category labels to. In work on the deep structure of sentences in natural language, which discipline influences categorial ontology, the most basic chosen labels/categories are names and sentences. Cresswell's syntax involves the use of angle brackets ⟨ ⟩ and category labels 0, 1. Slightly confusingly, according to Cresswell's approach it's the name that is '1' and the sentence that is '0':

(Cresswell, M. J., 'Categorial Languages', Studia Logica 36 (1977), 257-269.)
The term 'functor' can be confusing in this context, since it is a term of art and technical term in linguistics denoting function words: words with little or no semantic content that are used to bind and combine semantically richer words to build meaningful phrases, clauses, and sentences. In the context of a formal categorial language, however, the term 'functor' denotes - in accordance with the definition in logic and algebra - a morphism between mathematical and/or logical categories.

According to Cresswell's deployment of Lesniewski's system, John is a name (1), and runs is an intransitive verb. Thus runs would be in category ⟨ 0,1 ⟩ because it takes/maps a name to a sentence. The two place transitive verb loves is in ⟨ 0,1,1 ⟩ because it takes two names (e.g. Chris, category 1, and Naomi, category 1) to a sentence (category 0) 'Chris loves Naomi'.

The same approach applies to categories where what is labelled is logical truth functional connectives and operators. Thus logical negation ~ is category ⟨ 0,0 ⟩ because it will take a logical sentence to another sentence: 

'All frogs are amphibians' 
∀x(Fx → Ax) 

becomes another sentence 

'All frogs are not amphibians'
~∀x(Fx → Ax) 

And, as stated above, sentences are category label 0.

(Cresswell, M. J., 'Categorial Languages', Studia Logica 36 (1977), 257-269.)

The treatment in the above quotations from reference #3 is, perhaps, not as clear as it could be. Cresswell's presentation in another paper (reference #4) is superior. In the following excerpt, the lambda calculus abstraction of Alonzo Church is introduced. This presentation makes it clearer how the complex categories work. The first term in the brackets is the 'output' category term or the result category:

(Cresswell, M. J. (1980). Quotational Theories of Propositional Attitudes. Journal of Philosophical Logic9(1), 17–40. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00258075)

Note that there is an editorial/typographical error (missing angle bracket) at the category definition of the ∀. It should read:

F⟨ 0, ⟨ 0,1⟩⟩ = {∀}
Cresswell continues to develop the formal language, introducing the lambda λ-abstraction symbol which enables working with functions as arguments of functions, and which is also motivated by the need to exclude set theoretic ontological considerations from the formalism:


Church's lambda  λ here serves to denote that the application of the function expression α to the variable x.


The purpose of the lambda calculus and notation is to provide an alternative way of defining functions for λ-categorial languages: non-extensionally as a parameter or argument expression instead of extensionally as a set of ordered pairs corresponding to a morphism. Its use is straightforward once the category language apparatus as described above is in place. Instead of defining a function in set-theoretic terms, one specifies an expression α in the logical language, and then treats both the expression and the variable for the values x as arguments. The λ simply denotes this application of expression argument to variable argument.



It's called λ-abstraction because the expression is treated as an argument that can take any specified value and with no function name - only an expression. In functional computer languages this is also referred to as an anonymous function. No function definition is used and so no morphism between sets or set of ordered pairs is picked out as an extension. In this way, the function expression can be used as an argument passed to a function or ⟨λ, x, a ⟩ expression in λ-categorial languages  I'll not pursue further investigation of the lambda calculus here.

What's of further interest in this post is Bigelow and Leckey's adaptation of the Dσ notation for domains of properties and relations of individuals:




Bigelow and Leckey denote a domain of individuals/particulars as

Dι

Thence, for properties, they "read ‘D⟨ ι ⟩’ as signifying the domain for ‘properties that [are] instantiated by things in the category Dι ’":

D⟨ ι 


and then for the domain of properties of those properties:

D⟨⟨ ι ⟩⟩


and so on, recursively ad infinitum, while relations between any of the individuals and properties in these categories are denoted by:


Dh, k, ... 
‘the category for relations among things in categories h, k, …'
and:

'For instance, if we might set the variables h = ι and k = ⟨ι⟩. Then
D⟨ h, k ⟩ = D⟨ ι, ⟨ ι ⟩⟩
And, in that case, ‘D⟨ ι, ⟨ ι ⟩⟩’ is to read as the category for‘ relations between individuals and properties of individuals’. (From Bigelow, J, and Leckey, M., 2018 Categorial Ontology URL https://aap.org.au/ABSTRACTS-2018)
Bigelow and Leckey's adaptation of the Cresswell-Lesniewski syntax for property and relation categories is syntactically elegant. It does render the semantics into a manageable and compact form of syntactic expression that allows for tidy representation. However, I suspect that any deployment of comprehensive logical proofs will involve what I will call a 'LISP' effect for longer proofs, according to which outcome (see next paragraph) the proof would become difficult to follow and read due to nesting of parentheses. It's a style and readability issue, potentially.

 λ-calculus was the inspiration for a number of functional computer programming languages in the 1970s and 1980s (with a recent resurgence in interest with programming languages like Microsoft's F#.) One of the known problems with some of these languages was human readability for complex programs. The acronym LISP literally stands for 'Lots of Irritating Silly Parentheses'. It's not for nothing that there is a 'LISP showoff page' on Wiki:

LISP code excerpt from Wiki 
For those not familiar with procedural computer programming: much like logical proofs, any slip is death when it comes to syntax (and with computer code that can mean the aircraft traffic control systems!) Tracking the number of parentheses on the left and right is no longer a manual task in most programming IDEs (integrated [software] development environments), but when LISP was introduced to the world, things were less sophisticated and programmers had to count the parentheses and check their placement to ensure that the code would compile, and that if it did the logic was right.  If a logician is not using a CA tool for proofs in logic, then the same situation prevails for readability and robustness in The point is that some formal logics have readability and clarity challenges, and Bigelow and Leckey's multiple nested ⟨ ⟩'s might become cumbersome. I should provide an experimental proof to test this speculation, but I will defer this until another day due to time and space constraints.

Potential Vagueness Problems

Leckey and Bigelow are aware of the challenges for their Platonic variety of realism about properties and relations. They bite the bullet on the Platonic commitments, and echo the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument for the realist commitments their categorial ontology, recursively replete as it is with properties of, and relations between, any and all of the possible elements in all available categories.

As with all formal language development, category languages involve problems and challenges. These are historically well known.

Bigelow and Leckey address issues of definitional in-exactitude for names in both natural and formal languages, referring to the work of semanticists in their treatment of the deep structure of natural languages, and to the closely related work of logicians interested in applying categorial languages to capture deep-structure natural language semantics and to provide an ontological basis and semantics for a formal logic.

In first order logic, only individuals, predicates, and names (for specific token individuals) are admitted: one can have a predicate and apply it to a variable or else to a name a. Importantly, in natural language:
there are syntactic categories approximately shadowing the names, variables, and predicates of the predicate calculus; but there are complications. The syntactic category for nouns, for instance, behaves in some respects as if these were names; but often we translate nouns into predicates when we regiment our assertions in the predicate calculus   
(From Bigelow, J, and Leckey, M., 2018 Categorial Ontology URL https://aap.org.au/ABSTRACTS-2018)
In linguistic (natural language) semantics (as opposed to the logical-philosophical variety for formal languages and the study of meaning itself), theorists attempt to identify the deep structure of the meaning of sentences and how it relates to the surface structure. The classifications of nouns and natural language terms in formal categorial language hierarchy is often not straightforward.

Leckey and Bigelow, like Cresswell, also identify ambiguous syncategorematic terms in natural language as being problematic for a formal categorial language treatment because they do not seem to belong to one category only:
"Deviations of human language from ontological stratification:

In framing a description of a stratified categorial ontology, some of the words we have been employing do not invite interpretation by assigning to them a single thing, as a ‘semantic value’ or ‘meaning’. They seem, instead, to scatter their reference across more than one, sometimes perhaps infinitely many, distinct ontological categories.
Thus, for instance, our use of the word ‘property’ resists the assignment to any one unique ‘semantic value’, which could be located within any one domain of properties within the ontological hierarchy. Instead, the word ‘property’ seems to cast a scattered reference all the way up the hierarchy.

...Wittgenstein...suggested that there may be ‘family resemblance’ concepts that spread their reference by a recursive pattern that might work roughly like this.We might apply the word ‘game’ to something with salient characteristics A, B and C. Something new comes along with salient characteristics B, C and D. So we apply the same word to this new thing. And so on. Eventually we apply the same word to something with salient characteristics P, Q and R, which has no salient properties in common with the things that we initially called games because they have properties A, B and C.
A similar pattern can be elicited concerning our theoretical applications of the word ‘property’. We apply the word ‘property’ to things in category D⟨ ι ⟩ because they stand in a relation that we call ‘being instantiated by’ to the individuals that are found in the domain Dι

Then, at categorial levels just a few steps higher – say, categories D⟨ h ⟩  and Dh  – we will find a relationship that resembles the ‘instantiation’ relationship between D⟨ ι ⟩  and Dι . Consequently, we transfer the reference of the words ‘being instantiated by’ up to that level as well. This recursive mechanism will smear the reference of the linguistic expressions ‘property’ and ‘is instantiated by’ all the way up the hierarchy, by a process that closely echoes Wittgenstein’s conception of a ‘family resemblance’. "
(From Bigelow, J, and Leckey, M., 2018 Categorial Ontology URL https://aap.org.au/ABSTRACTS-2018) 
Cresswell notes that some category language theorists have introduced features that allow multi-category expressions:


Again here there is some difficult typography.
"...for any function a in D⟨0,1⟩  , ζ(a) is the function such that for any x in D1 (ζ(a) = ω(a(x)) 

Syncategorematic natural language represents a problem for category language. However, I think that one other possible related challenge for this kind of categorial language and ontology arises due to logical vagueness (common examples include identifying at exactly what point on a colour spectrum dark red becomes purple, or at what number of hairs a person attains the property of baldness). They are related to this kind of syncategorematic language ambiguity, but are not the same.

One example hinted at by Bigelow and Leckey themselves is that of the property of being approximately spherical, with a matching category for all of the individuals that are approximately spherical. Now, the natural language label for this category is easily stated. However, it would seem to be a requirement of categorial language and ontology of the kind Bigelow and Leckey desire that the categories be unambiguous and distinct,even if the semantic content of certain terms is spread across them. Yet, I suspect that the obvious sorites paradox associated with the concept of approximate sphericity (at what point does some geometric object that is not spherical become approximately spherical, and how is this decided and why?) troubles the base category of individuals, and by recursion all of the categories containing instantiations of property and relations that are based upon the category of individuals.

It's not so much that the property of being approximately spherical is cross-category in terms of expression that refer to it (it may well be so). It's not that it involves a progressive family resemblance problem such that the surface meaning of the term has slipped or migrated across deep meaning categories. It's that the property itself is ineliminably vague. Thus the category - against the requirements for category language categories - is also vague or perhaps undefinable in the right way. Why do I surmise that this might be a problem for Leckey and Bigelow? Because their proposed category ontology is supposed to be superior to, and more coherent than, those ontologies associated with formal languages which do not admit such a wide range of Platonic entities onto the menu of existing things.

There are pathological cases and problematic cases for all formal logics. Bertrand Russell's own paradox of FOL is perhaps the locus classicus example.

The domain for the property instantiated by the property of being approximately spherical would seem to be dead on arrival. Moreover, it is not clear what happens to the 'is instantiated by' relation and its domain in this case. Perhaps this pathological case is not something that should be admitted into consideration.

Perhaps the members of the set of approximately spherical things will have to be a Zadehian fuzzy set, given that adducing exactly when something crosses the threshold between approximately spherical, and not approximately spherical, might be prohibitive.

References


  1. Bigelow, John, (1988), The Reality of Numbers: A Physicalist’s Philosophy of Mathematics, Oxford: Clarendon.
  2. From Bigelow, J, and Leckey, M., 2018 Categorial Ontology URL https://aap.org.au/ABSTRACTS-2018)
  3. Cresswell, M. J., (1977) 'Categorial Languages', Studia Logica 36 , 257-269.
  4. Cresswell, M. J. (1980). Quotational Theories of Propositional Attitudes. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 9(1), 17–40. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00258075
  5. Linnebo, Ø. (2018). Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/platonism-mathematics/
  6. Gallin, D. (1977). Review: M. J. Cresswell, Logics and Languages. J. Symbolic Logic, 42(iss. 3), 425–426.
  7. Rennie, M. K. (1974). CRESSWELL, M. J.: “Logics and Languages” (Book Review). Australasian Journal of Philosophy52(Generic), 277.



Sunday, 26 August 2018

Is biology the only or correct source for answering the question 'What is the Human?' ? Ask these Dudes...

Wednesday, 25 July 2018

Wolfgang Iser's 'Secret' Source for Repertoire and the Interdisciplinarity of The Philosophy of Information

Philosophers of information are used to the ready interdisciplinarity that the subdiscipline both avails, and demands, of the researcher. This is due to many factors including the polysemous content of the term 'information' itself, the general intuitive and practical importance of information (on a par with such things as knowledge and structure, and related intimately to both) and the general recognition of the validity and salience of pluralist conceptions of information.

I intend to make this short post one in a series of 'who knows' how many on interdisciplinarity in the philosophy of information.

When I first embarked upon my Master of Philosophy in English at The University of Sydney, I had only recently completed an Honours First Class in Philosophy and been admitted to a PhD in philosophy. A flight of literary fancy took me and I decided to try a lateral and interdisciplinary move to English. Dr Peter Marks suggested that I use the topic of my Honours thesis as a jumping-off point. I was surprised at this suggestion, since the Honours thesis was significantly orientated towards the philosophy of information and probability: more philosophy of science and analytic philosophy in the Anglo-American vein.

I should have realised that Professor Marks knew what was afoot. I had only just met him and was not aware that I was talking to an eminent Orwell scholar from Oxford with a famous thesis about Orwell.

It transpires that Shannon's appeal in his editorial address in the 1956 edition of IEEE Transactions was a response to a trend of literary theorists and social scientists to embrace - metaphorically, analogically, and otherwise - the ideas of Shannon's very much applied scientific and statistical Mathematical Theory of Communication:

The Bandwagon (1956)
The Bandwagon Article can be found here and at this nice blogopedia Wiki based article from which I learned that the Sokal hoax article in fact draws parodically upon Shannon's article.
In Shannon's 1948 applied statistical theory, there are causal information sources (Shannon's physical stochastic processes and in-model representations of the same) and then there are complex polysemantic combined information sources which include the properties of Shannon sources, but also include dynamical situations and data structures that have pre-encoded epistemic and cognitive, linguistic, then political and ideological semantic information/content. Sounds overly fixated upon information theory and somewhat over-analytical or 'scientistic' - right?

Perhaps not. Wolfgang Iser's reader reception theory was built upon the foundation of the idea of repertoire. Repertoires are the sets of texts (using literary theoretic parlance) that influence the reader's  partial construction of parsed and interpreted texts and their associated narratives (where a narrative can be construed broadly as semantic and epistemic context and content). As is the case with most theories - especially those in the arts and humanities - the core idea came from elsewhere. It came from a little known French analytic philosopher and polymath by the name of Abram Moles. Moles' primary interest was in what is sometimes called computational aesthetics. He attempted to use Claude E. Shannon's conception of information sources and transmission in an analysis of texts and textual transmission (a not uncommon trend in the mid to late 20th century).

Abraham Moles

Moles

This influence of Shannon upon the work of structuralist literary theorists, grammarians, and social scientists is also revealed in the work of structuralists John Lyons and Zellig S. Harris. Harris was a true informationist interdisciplinarian, producing works analysing the information content of specific scientific language, formulating one of the first semantic theories of information, and even producing  an informational analysis of scientific structures in molecular bioscience/immunlogy (11 and 12 below.)

That information theory influences late structuralist and early poststructuralist and postmodern theory by way of Iser's work is borne out by those theorists investments in effort to apply information theory to grammar, linguistics, and literary theory:


From an interview with Wolfgang Iser

Notice that the references to instructions (and the execution thereof), codes, information, and feed-back all draw heavily upon the discourses of Wienerian cybernetics and Shannonian information theory as well as the emerging computer sciences of the time. Those readers familiar with the science of computer architecture will recognise that instruction processing and microcodes are the stuff of earlier microcode based CPU architectures.

More recently in history, new efforts have also arisen in the other scholarly direction - from critical theory to information theory with the former applied to the implications and effects of the latter. Fuchs work clearly reflects the style and discourse of lat 20th century neo-marxist continental philosophers.


Again the discursive admixture of very continental (and in this case neomarxist) and literary theoretic modes with that of the information sciences is striking, if not unexpected. The proposed meta-theoretic critical discipline is a natural, yet clever and inventive, evolution of the tool set of critical theory.

The philosophy of information lends itself to and requires a breathtaking interdisciplinary breadth that is also constrained by a science-humanities conceptual nexus rooted in applied science as significant as The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Professor Peter Marks had seen the influence of information theory on structuralism and poststructuralism first hand, and had a ready repertoire for a beginner to apply himself too.

Bibliography

  1. Allmer, T. (2012). Towards a Critical Theory of Surveillance in Informational Capitalism. Frankfurt: Lang, Peter, GmbH, Internationaler Verlag der Wissenschaften. 
  2. Baddeley, R., & Attewell, D. (2009). The Relationship Between Language and the Environment: Information Theory Shows Why We Have Only Three Lightness Terms. Psychological Science, 20(9), 1100–1107. 
  3. Bar-Hillel, Y. (1964). Language and information: selected essays on their theory and application. Reading, Mass: Addison-Wesley. 
  4. Cooper, W. S. (1978). Foundations of logico-linguistics: a unified theory of information, language, and logic (Vol. 2). Dordrecht, Holland;Boston; D. Reidel Pub. Co. 
  5. De Bruyn, B. (2012). Wolfgang Iser: A Companion (Vol. 1). Berlin ;Boston: De Gruyter. 
  6. Fuchs, C. (2009). Towards a critical theory of information. TripleC: Communication, Capitalism & Critique, 7(2). https://doi.org/10.31269/triplec.v7i2.91
  7. Harris, Z. S. (1951). Structural linguistics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 
  8. Harris, Z. S. (1962). String analysis of sentence structure (Vol. no. 1). The Hague: Mouton. 
  9. Harris, Z. S. (1982). A grammar of English on mathematical principles. New York: Wiley. 
  10. Harris, Z. S. (1988). Language and information (Vol. no. 28). New York: Columbia University Press. 
  11. Harris, Z. S. (1989). The Form of information in science: analysis of an immunology sublanguage (Vol. 104). Dordrecht [Netherlands];Boston; Kluwer Academic Publishers. 
  12. Harris, Z. S. (1991). A theory of language and information: a mathematical approach. Oxford [England];New York; Clarendon Press. 
  13. Harris, Z. S. (2002). The structure of science information. Journal of Biomedical Informatics, 35(4), 215–221. 
  14. Iser, W. (1974). The implied reader: patterns of communication in prose fiction from Bunyan to Beckett. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. 
  15. Iser, W. (1978). The act of reading: a theory of aesthetic response. London [etc.]: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 
  16. Jauss, H. R., & De Man, P. (1982). Toward an aesthetic of reception (Vol. 2). Brighton: Harvester. 
  17. LEE, R. (2010). The use of information theory to determine the language character type of Pictish symbols. Scottish Archaeological Journal, 32(2), 137–176. 
  18. Lodwick, W. A., & Thipwiwatpotjana, P. (2017). Generalized uncertainty theory: A language for information deficiency. Studies in Computational Intelligence, 696, 37–69. 
  19. Lyons, J., Newman, S., Sapir, P., Swiggers, P., & Zellig, S. H. (2008). General Linguistics (Vol. I). Berlin ;Boston: De Gruyter Mouton. 
  20. Montemurro, M. A., & Zanette, D. (2009). Towards the quantification of the semantic information encoded in written language. 
  21. Pereira, F. (2000). Formal grammar and information theory: together again? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 358(1769), 1239–1253. 
  22. PLOTKIN, J. B., & NOWAK, M. A. (2000). Language Evolution and Information Theory. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 205(1), 147–159. 
  23. Shannon, C. (1956). The bandwagon (Edtl.). IRE Transactions on Information Theory, 2(1), 3–3. 
  24. Whitworth, A. (2006). Communicative competence in the information age: Towards a critical theory of information literacy education. Innovation in Teaching and Learning in Information and Computer Sciences, 5(1), 1–13.

Monday, 16 July 2018

The NZAP Conference, and Lesser Known and Rising Stars of The Philosophy of Information...

NZAP 2018


I recently attended, and enjoyed speaking at, the NZAP conference at Victoria University of Wellington in wonderful Wellington, New Zealand.

The organisers of the event did a stellar job:




Aside from somehow managing to be sick for the first two days, sleeping 10 hours a day, I had a great experience there. I met Dr Doug Campbell of Canterbury University in Christchurch, who presented a talk on the shortcomings of Frank Jackson's conception of physicalism, and showed how to reconcile it with the Chalmers-Papineau 'totalist' conception to arrive at a superior restatement of the latter. I am currently reviewing the paper for his talk and preparing a similar paper of my own based upon an informational restatement of Jackson's conception as presented in my PhD thesis last year.

I was also pleased to again run into Dr Martin Leckey and Professor John Bigelow, who presented a very interesting notation for hierarchical categorical ontology, which I have adduced is apt to be used for my own virtual-concrete information source ontology:




I am looking forward to completing a joint project with Dr Leckey.

Philosophers of Information in Ascension


I also had the pleasure of meeting the first of three very talented lesser known and/or upcoming philosophers of information whose work I would like to introduce:

Dr Anton Sukhoverkhov


Anton is interested in biosemiotics and Natural Signs and The Origins of Language. I have joined Dr Sukhoverkhov in contributing to a joint working group paper on different perspectives on the nature of information. He specialises also in ontology of memory and the role of non-genetic inheritance in biological and social evolution.

Dr Sukhoverkhov is particularly interested in the nature of information in natural phenomena and what makes such information semantic. He is currently situated at Macquarie University on a six month fellowship coming off the back of a Fullbright Scholarship to the US.

Sukhoverkhov Bibliography

Sukhoverkhov, Anton. 2010. “Memory, Sign Systems, and Self-Reproductive Processes.” Biological Theory 5 (2): 161–66.
———. 2012. “Natural Signs and the Origin of Language.” Biosemiotics 5 (2): 153–59.
Sukhoverkhov, Anton V., and Carol A. Fowler. 2015. “Why Language Evolution Needs Memory: Systems and Ecological Approaches.” Biosemiotics 8 (1): 47–65.

See more here.



Dr Simon D'Alfonso




My co-author on a current working paper about social mindreading, the small network model and the extended mind, Simon has produced an important logical analysis of Fred Dretske's classically derived and adapted conception of information flow. Dretske's model involves an adaptation of the classical Shannonian model of The Mathematical Theory of Communication that is designed to facilitate a proposal for a reliabilist epistemology based upon a naturalised conception of information. Dretske's adaptation involves singling out the information measure - according to the Shannonian probabilistic conception - of the information content of a single signal. It removes the averaging over sequences of symbols and messages that is necessary in Shannon's system and for Shannon's averaging measure of entropy of a sequence.

In particular the analysis reveals the problematic nature of Dretske's 'k' factor: or the 'knowledge' that the receiver has about the possible states of the source or the possibilities at the source. It's this factor that I have variously identified as being what makes Dretske's otherwise naturalised objectivist conception of information into a subjectivist conception. However, it does so when Dretske deploys the initial objective conception from the perspective of a receiver in order to develop a conception of semantic information.

D'Alfonso identifies that the 'k' factor complicates the proposal of a logic of objective information flow by disrupting minimal algebraic properties required for such to be useful: complementarity for example.

D'Alfonso Bibliography

D’Alfonso, Simon. 2011. “On Quantifying Semantic Information.” Information 2 (4): 61–101.
———. 2014. “The Logic of Knowledge and the Flow of Information.” Minds and Machines 24 (3): 307–25.
———. 2016. “Belief Merging with the Aim of Truthlikeness.” Synthese 193 (7): 2013–2034.


Professor Wu Kun


Professor Wu Kun warrants mention because he is perhaps the only Chinese interdisciplinary and comparative philosopher working in the field of the philosophy of information who has been doing so since the 1980s. In fact I am writing a commentary and paper in support of and response to a number of the professor's views.

Professor Wu Kun Bibliography



Kun, Wu, and Joseph E. Brenner. 2015. “An Informational Ontology and Epistemology of Cognition.” Foundations of Science 20 (3): 249–279.